Студопедия
Случайная страница | ТОМ-1 | ТОМ-2 | ТОМ-3
АвтомобилиАстрономияБиологияГеографияДом и садДругие языкиДругоеИнформатика
ИсторияКультураЛитератураЛогикаМатематикаМедицинаМеталлургияМеханика
ОбразованиеОхрана трудаПедагогикаПолитикаПравоПсихологияРелигияРиторика
СоциологияСпортСтроительствоТехнологияТуризмФизикаФилософияФинансы
ХимияЧерчениеЭкологияЭкономикаЭлектроника

The who problem: what is the entity that has conscious experience?

Читайте также:
  1. A Case of Identity
  2. According to IAS 16, for accounting of PPE items an entity may choose between
  3. Announcing Identity
  4. BLISS MACHINES: IS CONSCIOUS EXPERIENCE A GOOD IN ITSELF?
  5. CHAPTER TWENTY-EIGHT: THE TERRIBLE CURSE OF THE CONSCIOUSNESS OF FAME
  6. CONSCIOUSNESS TECHNOLOGIES AND THE IMAGE OF HUMANKIND
  7. Corporate Identity

Consciousness is always bound to an individual first-person perspective; this is part of what makes it so elusive. It is a subjective phenomenon. Someone has it. In a deep and indisputable way, your inner world truly is not just someone’s inner world but your inner world — a private realm of experience that only you have direct access to.

The conscious mind is not a public object — or such is the orthodox view, which may yet be overthrown by the Consciousness Revolution. In any event, the orthodox view holds that scientific research can be conducted only on objects exhibiting properties that are, at least in principle, observable to all of us. Green No. 24 is not. Neither is the distinct sensory quality of the scent of mixed amber and sandalwood, nor is your empathic experience of understanding the emotions of another human being when you see him in tears. Brain states, on the other hand, are observable. Brain states also clearly have what philosophers call representational content. There are receptive fields for the various sensory stimuli. We know where emotional content originates, and we have good candidates for the seat of episodic memory in the brain, and so on.

Conscious experience has content, too — phenomenal content — and I touched upon it in the Introduction: Its phenomenal content is its subjective character — how an experience privately and inwardly feels to you, what it is like to have it. But this particular content, it seems, is accessible only to a single person — you, the experiencing subject. And who is that?

To form a successful theory of consciousness, we must match firstperson phenomenal content to third-person brain content. We must somehow reconcile the inner perspective of the experiencing self with the outside perspective of science. And there will always be many of us who intuitively think this can never be done. Many people think consciousness is ontologically irreducible (as philosophers say), because first-person facts cannot be reduced to third-person facts. It is more likely, however, that consciousness is epistemically irreducible (as philosophers say). The idea is simple: One reality, one kind of fact, but two kinds of knowledge: first-person knowledge and third-person knowledge. Even though consciousness is a physical process, these two different forms of knowing can never be conflated. Knowing every last thing about a person’s brain states will never allow us to know what they are like for the person herself. But the concept of a first-person perspective turns out to be vague the moment we take a close look at it. What is this mysterious first person? What does the word “I” refer to? If not simply to the speaker, does it refer to anything in the known world at all? Is the existence of an experiencing self a necessary component of consciousness? I don’t think it is — for one thing, because there seem to be “self-less” forms of conscious experience. In certain severe psychiatric disorders, such as Cotard’s syndrome, patients sometimes stop using the first-person pronoun and, moreover, claim that they do not really exist. M. David Enoch and William Trethowan have described such cases in their book Uncommon Psychiatric Syndromes: “Subsequently the subject may proceed to deny her very existence, even dispensing altogether with the use of the personal pronoun ‘I’. One patient even called herself ‘Madam Zero’ in order to emphasize her non-existence. One [patient] said, referring to herself, ‘It’s no use. Wrap it up and throw “it” in the dustbin’.”18

Mystics of all cultures and all times have reported deep spiritual experiences in which no “self” was present, and some of them, too, stopped using the pronoun “I.” Indeed, many of the simple organisms on this planet may have a consciousness tunnel with nobody living in it. Perhaps some of them have only a consciousness “bubble” instead of a tunnel, because, together with the self, awareness of past or future disappears as well.

Note that up to now, in defining the problems for a grand unified theory of consciousness, we have assumed only a minimalist notion: the appearance of a world. But as you are reading these sentences, not only is the light on but there is also somebody home. Human consciousness is characterized by various forms of inwardness, all of which influence one another: First, it is an internal process in the nervous system; second, it creates the experience of being in a world; third, the virtual window of presence gives us temporal internality, a Now. But the deepest form of inwardness was the creation of an internal self/world border.

In evolution, this process started physically, with the development of cell membranes and an immune system to define which cells in one’s body were to be treated as one’s own and which were intruders.19 Billions of years later, nervous systems were able to represent this self/world distinction on a higher level — for instance, as body boundaries delineated by an integrated but as yet unconscious body schema. Conscious experience then elevated this fundamental strategy of partitioning reality to a previously unknown level of complexity and intelligence. The phenomenal self was born, and the conscious experience of being someone gradually emerged. A self-model, an inner image of the organism as a whole, was built into the world-model, and this is how the consciously experienced first-person perspective developed.

How to comprehend subjectivity is the deepest puzzle in consciousness research. In order to overcome it, we must understand how the conscious self was born into the tunnel, how nature managed to evolve a centered model of reality, creating inner worlds that not only appear but that appear to someone. We must understand how the consciousness tunnel turned into an Ego Tunnel.


Дата добавления: 2015-10-31; просмотров: 158 | Нарушение авторских прав


Читайте в этой же книге: A Note on the Footnotes | ACKNOWLEDGMENTS | THE PHENOMENAL SELF-MODEL | THE APPEARANCE OF A WORLD | THE ONE-WORLD PROBLEM: THE UNITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS | THE NOW PROBLEM: A LIVED MOMENT EMERGES | THE REALITY PROBLEM: HOW YOU WERE BORN AS A NAIVE REALIST | THE INEFFABILITY PROBLEM: WHAT WE WILL NEVER BE ABLE TO TALK ABOUT | OUT OF THE BODY AND INTO THE MIND | THE OUT-OF-BODY EXPERIENCE |
<== предыдущая страница | следующая страница ==>
THE EVOLUTION PROBLEM: COULDN’T ALL OF THIS HAVE HAPPENED IN THE DARK?| THE UNITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS: A CONVERSATION WITH WOLF SINGER

mybiblioteka.su - 2015-2024 год. (0.006 сек.)