|
Let us begin with categories. First, categories can be fuzzy; they can have shaded borders. What is a rich person? There are clear "cases, but no absolute income line clearly demarcates rich from non-rich. There is a gradation. There are no clear boundaries here. One can artificially impose them, of course. But then one could impose them in another way just as well. Consider a moral rule like The rich should help the poor." If person A does not help person B, it is not always clear whether the rule is being violated.
Fuzzy categories like "rich" and "poor" regularly appear in moral rules. One can always draw lines in one way or another—below this line is poor, above that line is rich. But where one draws these lines is a matter of interpretation and discretion, just what a strictly absolute morality cannot tolerate.
Second, categories can be radial, as in the case of a mother. Suppose you have lots of mothers of various kinds. A genetic mother (who donated the egg that formed you). A birth mother (who bore you). Your father's wife at the time of your birth, who raised you. And your father’s second wife, your step-mother. How do you know if you have obeyed the commandment 'Respect thy mother’ Which mother? All of them? Even the egg donor you've never met?
Even the birth mother you haven't seen since you left the womb? Of course the meaning of mother has changed since the time of the commandment. And that is the point. Meanings change in this way constantly. Most categories are radial. If the concept undergoing change is part of a moral rule, then the rule is not clear and unequivocal. It will require interpretation. But there are always different possibilities for interpretation. And that makes the rule not strict and unequivocal. It means the rule defines not one path but many possible ones.
Third, there are prototype effects. Suppose you have a stereotype of athletes as dumb and you are in charge of admissions to a major university. This is, of course, a false stereotype, just as all stereotypes by their very nature are false. Suppose you feel that this places a moral obligation on you not to admit dumb people into the university. Suppose you do, under alumni pressure, admit athletes. Have you violated your self-imposed moral obligation?
The problem is this: Rules contain categories (e.g., dumb people). People usually have stereotypes for thousands of their categories. It is completely normal (though may be not nice) for people to reason in terms of stereotypes. Because different people have different stereotypes, they will understand a category differently and reason about it differently. That means that they will understand a moral rule containing that category differently. In short, the fact that people really do reason about categories on the basis of stereotypes violates the condition that the meaning of a rule must be invariant from person to person and occasion to occasion. The mind just doesn't work that way.
Incidentally, stereotype-based reasoning is only one form of a much more widespread phenomenon called "prototype-based reasoning." We have seen other examples of prototype-based reasoning in this book. One type is reasoning in terms of ideal cases, as when one thinks about conservatives or liberals in terms of an ideal model of conservatives or liberals. Another type is reasoning on the basis of demons, or anti-ideals. We have seen plenty of cases of demon-based reasoning throughout this book. Another case is called "salient exemplar" reasoning, where one takes a well-known case to stand for a whole category. This is common throughout political and moral discourse.
Fuzzy categories, radial categories, stereotypes, and other forms of prototype-based reasoning all introduce meaning variability. Radial categories are produced, in large measure, because categories do change over time, and their extensions over time are often preserved in radial category structure.
Framing
Alternative framing possibilities also provide for forms of everyday variation in meaning. Consider an example from my colleague Charles Fillmore (see References, sec. A3). Suppose you have a friend named Harry who doesn't like to spend much money. You could conceptualize him and describe him in two very different ways. You could say either " He's thrifty " or " He's stingy. " Both sentences indicate that he doesn't spend much money, but the first frames that fact in terms of the issue of resource preservation (thrift), while the second frames the issue in terms of generosity (stinginess).
Now imagine an invocation that says: Spend as little money as possible. This is the message that a balanced budget amendment would send to Congress. There are three ways to interpret this invocation: Either "Be thrifty" or "Be stingy" or both. Liberals argue that the government should be thrifty but not stingy. Conservatives argue, on the basis of Strict Father morality, that thriftiness in government is never stinginess, since cutting off government funding just makes people more self-disciplined and self-reliant and so is good for them.
The point is that such an invocation, which is a very real invocation, has two interpretations depending on framing. Moreover, the meaning of that framing depends on world-view, as we have seen throughout this book. But Strict Father morality demands a view of the human mind in which such framing and worldview differences do not and cannot exist. Moral rules, in order to be moral rules, must be understandable in the same way to everybody. The very existence of different worldviews and different modes of framing shows that this is false. The human mind is such that framing differences and worldview differences really do exist, not just here and there in minor ways, but on a truly massive scale. The prohibition "Don't murder babies" may or may not apply to taking a morning-after pill, depending on whether a cluster of cells is framed as a "baby" and taking such a pill is framed as "murder."
Variability in meaning due to framing and worldview differences and to the properties of categories (fuzziness, radial structure, prototypes) creates such a huge meaning variability in normal, everyday human reasoning that the conditions needed for the Strict Father model to be coherent are just not met.
Дата добавления: 2015-10-30; просмотров: 88 | Нарушение авторских прав
<== предыдущая страница | | | следующая страница ==> |
THE HUMAN MIND | | | Imperfect Communication |