Студопедия
Случайная страница | ТОМ-1 | ТОМ-2 | ТОМ-3
АрхитектураБиологияГеографияДругоеИностранные языки
ИнформатикаИсторияКультураЛитератураМатематика
МедицинаМеханикаОбразованиеОхрана трудаПедагогика
ПолитикаПравоПрограммированиеПсихологияРелигия
СоциологияСпортСтроительствоФизикаФилософия
ФинансыХимияЭкологияЭкономикаЭлектроника

Rewarding Players Who Punish: A Perfect Folk Theorem for the Discounting Criterion.

Наказание карателя: Совершенная народная теорема для критерия гонки | Поощряющие игроки с наказанием: Совершенная народная теорема для критерия угасания. | Структура равновесия, совершенного по под-играм, для критерия угасания | Игры с конечным числом повторений | Finitely Repeated Games |


Читайте также:
  1. An example round with a group of 6 players.
  2. C) Complete the sentences by putting the verb into the past perfect.
  3. Chapter 3 - He Is A Perfectly Impossible Person
  4. Chapter XIII. PERFECTION OF THE HOUSE
  5. Choose the correct verb forms. Use Simple Past or the Present Perfect
  6. Complete the conversation between a mother (M) and her daughter (D). Put the verbs in brackets into the present perfect or past simple. Explain the use of the tenses.
  7. D) with Past Simple, Past Continuous or Past Perfect.

The strategy profile defined in the proof of Proposition 149.1, in which players are punished for failing to mete out the punishment that they are assigned, may fail to be a subgame perfect equilibrium when the players' preferences are represented by the discounting criterion. The reason is as follows. Under the strategy profile a player who fails to participate in a punishment that was supposed to last, say, periods, is himself punished for, say, periods, where may be much larger then . Further deviations may require even longer punishments, with the result that the strategies should be designed to carry out punishments that are unboundedly long. However slight the discounting, there may thus be some punishment that results in losses that can never be recovered. Consequently, the strategy profile may not be a subgame perfect equilibrium if the players' preferences are represented by the discounting criterion.

To establish an analog to Proposition 149.1 for the case that the players' preferences are represented by the discounting criterion, we construct a new strategy. In this strategy players who punish deviants as the strategy dictates are subsequently rewarded, making it worthwhile for them to complete their assignments. As in the previous section we construct a strategy profile only for the case in which the equilibrium path consists of the repetition of a single (strictly enforceable) outcome. The result requires a restriction on the set of games that is usually called full dimensionality.

Proposition 151.1 (Perfect folk theorem for the discounting criterion) Let be a strictly enforceable outcome of . Assume that there is a collection of strictly enforceable outcomes of such that for every player we have and for all . Then there exists such that for all there is a subgame perfect equilibrium of the – discounted infinitely repeated game of than generates the path in which for all .

Proof. The strategy profile in which each player uses the following machine is a subgame perfect equilibrium that supports the outcome in every period. The machine has three types of states. In state the action profile chosen by the players is . For each the state is a state of "reconciliation" that is entered after any punishment of player is complete; in this state the action profile that is chosen is . For each player and period between and some number that we specify later, the state is one in which there remain periods in which player is supposed to be punished; in this state every player other than takes the action , which holds down to his minmax payoff. If any player deviates in any state there is a transition to the state , (that is, the other players plan to punish player for periods). If in none of the periods of punishment there is a deviation by a single punisher the state changes to . The set of states serves as a system that punishes players who misbehave during a punishment phase: if player does not punish player as he is supposed to, then instead of the state becoming , in which the outcome is , player is punished for periods, after which the state becomes , in which the outcome is .

To summarize, the machine of player is defined as follows, where for convenience we write ; we specify later.

· Set of states .

· Initial state: .

· Output function: In choose . In choose if , and if .

· Transitions in response to an outcome :

o From stay in unless a single player deviated from , in which case move to .

o From :

§ If a single player deviated from then move to .

§ Otherwise move to if and to if

We now specify the values of and . As before, let be the maximum of over all and . We choose and to be large enough that all possible deviations are deterred. To deter a deviation of any player in any state we take large enough that for all i and all and choose where is close enough to that for all we have

(This condition is sufficient since for ). If a player deviates from for then he obtains at most in the period that he deviates followed by periods of and subsequently. If he does not deviate then he obtains for between and periods and subsequently. Thus to deter a deviation it is sufficient to choose close enough to one that for all we have

(Such a value of exists because of our assumption that if )

Exercise 152.1 Consider the three-player symmetric infinitely repeated game in which each player's preferences are represented by the discounting criterion and the constituent game is where for we have and for all .

d) Find the set of enforceable payoffs of the constituent game.

e) Show that for any discount factor the payoff of any player in any subgame perfect equilibrium of the repeated game is at least .

f) Reconcile these results with Proposition 151.1.


Дата добавления: 2015-11-14; просмотров: 46 | Нарушение авторских прав


<== предыдущая страница | следующая страница ==>
Punishing the Punisher: A Perfect Folk Theorem for the Overtaking Criterion| The Structure of Subgame Perfect Equilibria Under the Discounting Criterion

mybiblioteka.su - 2015-2024 год. (0.007 сек.)